Copyright (c) 2013 John L. Jerz

The Order of Things (Foucault, 1966, 1970, 1994)

Home
A Proposed Heuristic for a Computer Chess Program (John L. Jerz)
Problem Solving and the Gathering of Diagnostic Information (John L. Jerz)
A Concept of Strategy (John L. Jerz)
Books/Articles I am Reading
Quotes from References of Interest
Satire/ Play
Viva La Vida
Quotes on Thinking
Quotes on Planning
Quotes on Strategy
Quotes Concerning Problem Solving
Computer Chess
Chess Analysis
Early Computers/ New Computers
Problem Solving/ Creativity
Game Theory
Favorite Links
About Me
Additional Notes
The Case for Using Probabilistic Knowledge in a Computer Chess Program (John L. Jerz)
Resilience in Man and Machine

FoucaultTOOT.jpg

When one defines "order" as a sorting of priorities, it becomes beautifully clear as to what Foucault is doing here. With virtuoso showmanship, he weaves an intensely complex history of thought. He dips into literature, art, economics and even biology in The Order of Things, possibly one of the most significant, yet most overlooked, works of the twentieth century.
 
Eclipsed by his later work on power and discourse, nonetheless it was The Order of Things that established Foucault's reputation as an intellectual giant. Pirouetting around the outer edge of language, Foucault unsettles the surface of literary writing. In describing the limitations of our usual taxonomies, he opens the door onto a whole new system of thought, one ripe with what he calls "exotic charm". Intellectual pyrotechnics from the master of critical thinking, this book is crucial reading for those who wish to gain insight into that odd beast called Postmodernism, and a must for any fan of Foucault.
 
JLJ - Explosive and deep concepts. Foucault seeks to expose the nature of reality - words and things - by tearing them down to basic, fundamental elements.

xv This passage quotes a ‘certain Chinese encyclopedia’ in which it is written that ‘animals are divided into: (a) belonging to the Emperor, (b) embalmed, (c) tame, (d) sucking pigs, (e) sirens, (f) fabulous, (g) stray dogs, (h) included in the present classification, (i) frenzied, (j) innumerable, (k) drawn with a very fine camelhair brush, (l) et cetera, (m) having just broken the water pitcher, (n) that from a long way off look like flies’ [JLJ - careful distinctions which had escaped me - I must be just plain ignorant]
 
p.40 The function proper to knowledge is not seeing or demonstrating; it is interpreting... There is more work in interpreting interpretations than in interpreting things
 
p.58-59 What is a sign...? ...Classical thought defines it according to three variables. First, the certainty of the relation: a sign may be so constant that one can be sure of its accuracy... but it may also be simply probable... Second, the type of relation: a sign may belong to the whole that it denotes (in the sense that a healthy appearance is part of the health it denotes) or be separate from it... Third, the origin of the relation: A sign may be natural... or conventional... These three variables replace resemblance in defining the sign's efficacity in the domains of empirical knowledge.
1. The sign, since it is always either certain or probable, should find its area of being within knowledge.
 
p.59 the whole domain of the sign is divided between the certain and the probable: that is to say, there can no longer be an unknown sign, a mute mark. This is not because men are in possession of all the possible signs, but because there can be no sign until there exists a known possibility of substitution between two known elements.
 
p.59 it is within knowledge itself that the sign is to perform its signifying function; it is from know­ledge that it will borrow its certainty or its probability.
 
p.60 The connection of ideas does not imply the relation of cause and effect, but only of a mark or sign with the thing signified. The fire which I see is not the cause of the pain I suffer upon my approaching it, but the mark that forewarns me of it.
 
p.60 For the sign to be, in effect, what it is, it must be presented as an object of knowledge at the same time as that which it signifies.
 
p.60-61 if one element of a perception is to become a sign for it, it is not enough merely for that element to be part of the perception; it must be differentiated qua element and be distinguished from the total impression with which it is confusedly linked; consequently, that total impression itself must have been divided up, and attention must have been directed towards one of the intermingled regions composing it, in order to isolate one of them. The constitution of the sign is thus inseparable from analysis. Indeed, it is the result of it, since without analysis the sign could not be­come apparent... Because the mind analyses, the sign appears. Because the mind has signs at its disposal, analysis never ceases.
 
p.61 The sign in classical thought does not erase distances or abolish time: on the contrary, it enables one to unfold them and to traverse them step by step. It is the sign that enables things to become distinct
 
p.63 the task of knowledge... its job now is to fabricate a language, and to fabricate it well - so that, as an instrument of analysis and combination, it will really be the language of calculation. [JLJ - Foucault here implies that knowledge creates a language of analytics, which might be useful for calculation, or for other purposes. We know, so that we might analyze, so that we might act on the signs we uncover.]
 
p.65  the sign is the representativity of the representation in so far as it is representable.
 
p.66 any analysis of signs is at the same time, and without need for further inquiry, the decipherment of what they are trying to say. Inversely, the discovery of what is signified is nothing more than a reflection upon the signs that indicate it.
 
p.66 There will therefore be no theory of signs separate and differing from an analysis of meaning... meaning cannot be anything more than the totality of the signs arranged in their progression
 
p.191 The one analyses value in terms of the exchange of objects of need - of useful objects; the other in terms of the formation and origin of objects whose exchange will later define their value
 
p.198 this equality of relation makes it possible to say, for example, that four measures of corn and five bundles of wood have an equal exchangeable value. But this equality does not mean that one exchanges utility for utility in identical portions: one exchanges inequalities, which means that on both sides - and despite the fact that each element traded has an intrinsic utility - more value is acquired than was originally possessed.
 
p.329 Economics was conceived on the basis of barter, because of his property and the other's property were equivalent; since they were offering satisfaction for almost identical desires, they were, in sum, 'alike'.

Enter supporting content here